Predicate Logic, Universal and Existential Quantifiers

(述語論理、全称限量子、存在限量子)

Discrete Mathematics I

7th lecture, November 9, 2018

http://www.sw.it.aoyama.ac.jp/2018/Math1/lecture7.html

Martin J. Dürst

AGU

© 2005-18 Martin J. Dürst Aoyama Gakuin University

Today's Schedule

 

Schedule for the Next Few Weeks

 

Announcement

There will be a minitest (ca. 30minutes) on November 30. Please start to prepare early!

 

Leftovers of Last Lecture

Summary of Last Lecture

 

Homework Due November 1, Problem 1

Sorry, it was removed! :)

 

Homework Due November 1, Problem 2

Sorry, it was removed! :)

 

Homework Due November 8, Problems 1/2

Sorry, it was removed! :)

 

Homework Due November 8, Problems 3/4

Sorry, it was removed! :)

 

Homework Due November 8, Problem 5

Sorry, it was removed! :)

 

Homework Due November 8, Problem 6

Sorry, it was removed! :)

 

Comments on Homework Corrections

(Homework due October 25)

 

About Returns of Tests and Homeworks

 

Types of Symbolic Logic

 

Limitations of Propositions

With propositions, related statements have to be made separately

Examples:
Today it is sunny. Tomorrow it is sunny. The day after tomorrow, it is sunny.
2 is even. 5 is even.

We can express "If today is sunny, then tomorrow will also be sunny." or "If 2 is even, then 3 is not even".

But we cannot express "If it's sunny on a given day, it's also sunny on the next day." or "If x is even, then x+2 is also even.".

 

Predicates

 

How to Write Predicates

There are two ways to write predicates:

  1. Functional notation:
  2. Operator notation:

 

Formulas Containing Predicates

Using predicates, we can express new things:

Similar to propositions, predicates can be true or false.

But predicates can also be unknown/undefined, for example if they contain variables.

Also, even if a predicate is undefined (e.g. even( x)),
a formula containing this predicate can be defined
(true, e.g. even(y) → even(y+2), or false, e.g. odd(z) → even(z+24))

 

First Order Predicate Logic

 

Universal Quantifier

Example: ∀n∈ℕ: even (n) → even(n+2)

Readings:

General form: ∀x: P (x)

∀ is the A of "for All", inverted.

Readings in Japanese:

 

Universal Quantifier for the Empty Set

x∈{}: P(x) = T

Reason:
We have to check P(x) for all elements x in the set.
If we find just one x where P(x) is false, the overall statement is false.
But we cannot find any x where P(x) is false.
Therefore, ∀x∈{}: P(x) is always true

Application example:

All students in this room from Hungary are over 50 (years old).
sS: native(s, Hungary) →age(s) > 50

See: Vacuous truth, https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Vacuous_truth

 

Knowledge about Field of Application

 

Existential Quantifier

Example: ∃n∈ℕ: odd (n)

Readings:

General form: ∃y: P (y)

∃ is the mirrored form of the E in "there Exists".

Readings in Japanese:

 

Structure of Quantifier Expressions

Example: ∀m, n∈ℕ: m > nm2n2

 

More Quantifier Examples

n∈ℕ: n + n + n = 3n

n∈ℕ: n2 = n3

n∈ℝ: n2 < 50n < n3

m, n∈ℕ: 7m + 2n = 2n + 7m

 

Peano Axioms in Predicate Logic

Peano Axioms (Guiseppe Peano, 1858-1932)

  1. 1∈ℕ
  2. a∈ℕ: s(a)∈ℕ
  3. ¬∃x∈ℕ: s(x) = 1
  4. a, b∈ℕ: abs(a) ≠ s(b)
  5. P(1) ∧ (∀k∈ℕ: (P(k)→P(s(k)))) ⇒ ∀a∈ℕ: P(a)

 

The Use of Variables with Quantifiers

Bound variable:
Variable quantified by a quantifier
Example: the x in: ∀x: (P(x)∧Q(y))
Free variable:
Variable not quantified by a quantifier
Example: the y in: ∀x: (P(x)∧Q(y))
Closed formula:
A formula without free variables.
Scope:
The part of a formula where a bound variable (or a quantifier) is active.
All occurrences of a bound variable within its scope can be exchanged by another variable.
Example: ∀s: (age(s)≤30 ∧ college(s)=CSE) ⇔ ∀u: (age(u)≤30 ∧ college(u)=CSE)
Using a bound variable outside its scope is an error.
Example: (∀x: P(x))∧Q(x)

  

Manipulation of Bound Variables

s: age(s)≤30) ∧ (∀t: college(t)=CSE) = ∀u: (age(u)≤30∧college(u)=CSE)

is the same as

s: age(s)≤30) ∧ (∀s: college(s)=CSE) = ∀s: (age(s)≤30∧college(s)=CSE)

There are three different variables s in the last statement.

Advice:

 

Important Points for Quantifiers

 

Laws for Quantifiers

  1. ¬∀x: P(x) = ∃x: ¬P(x)
  2. ¬∃x: P(x) = ∀x: ¬P(x)
  3. (X≠{}∧∀xX: P(x)) → (∃x: P(x))
  4. (∀x: P(x)) ∧ Q(y) = ∀x: P(x)∧Q(y)
  5. (∃x: P(x)) ∧ Q(y) = ∃x: P(x)∧Q(y)
  6. (∀x: P(x)) ∨ Q(y) = ∀x: P(x)∨Q(y)
  7. (∃x: P(x)) ∨ Q(y) = ∃x: P(x)∨Q(y)
  8. (∀x: P(x)) ∧ (∀x: R(x)) = ∀x: P(x)∧R(x)
  9. (∀x: P(x)) ∨ (∀x: R(x)) ⇒ ∀x: P(x)∨R(x)
  10. (∃x: P(x)) ∨ (∃x: R(x)) = ∃x: P(x)∨R(x)
  11. (∃x: P(x)) ∧ (∃x: R(x)) ⇐ ∃x: P(x)∧R(x)
  12. (∃y: ∀x: P(x, y)) ⇒ (∀x: ∃y: P(x, y))
  13. P(x) is a tautology ⇔∀x: P(x) is a tautology

 

Combination of Quantifiers

(∃y: ∀x: P(x, y)) → (∀x: ∃y: P(x, y))

(∀x: ∃y: P(x, y)) ↛ (∃y: ∀x: P(x, y))

The number of prime numbers is infinite.

(This means that whatever big number x we choose, there will always be a bigger prime number y.)

x: ∃y: (y > x ∧ prime(y))

Reversing the order of the quantifiers changes the meaning:

y: ∀x: (y > x ∧ prime(y))

(There is a prime number y that is bigger than any (natural number) x. This statement is obviously false.)

 

Proof that the Number of Prime Numbers is Infinite

  

This Week's Homework 1

Deadline: November 15, 2017 (Thursday), 19:00.

Format: Handout, easily readable handwriting

Where to submit: Box in front of room O-529 (building O, 5th floor)

Problems: See handout

 

Glossary

predicate logic
述語論理
quantifier
限量子
evaluate
評価する
evaluation
評価
array
配列
tautology
恒真 (式)、トートロジー
contradiction
恒偽 (式)
symbolic logic
記号論理
multi-valued logic
多値論理
fuzzy logic
ファジィ論理
ambiguity
曖昧さ
first-order predicate logic
一階述語論理
temporal logic
時相論理
binary logic
二値論理
generalization
一般化
argument
引数
undefined
未定
higher-order logic
高階述語論理
universal quantifier
全称限量子 (全称記号)
existential quantifier
存在限量子 (存在記号)
inference
推論
College of Science and Engineering
理工学部
native of ...
...出身
bound variable
束縛変数
free variable
自由変数
local variable
局所変数
closed formula
閉論理式
scope
作用領域、スコープ
prime number
素数